« The "If ___ means anything, it surely means ____" argument | Main | A lawyer show I'd watch »
Thursday, July 12, 2012
Is Religious Liberty Vulnerable, or is Religious Liberty Talk Too Insulated?
There have been some interesting freedom of religion discussions in the past day or two. Steve Smith, guesting at the CLR Forum, has a post inspired by Doug Laycock's recent article “Sex, Atheism, and the Free Exercise of Religion,” 88 Detroit-Mercy L. Rev. 407 (2011). Laycock writes in that article that “[f]or the first time in nearly 300 years, important forces in American society are questioning the free exercise of religion in principle– suggesting that free exercise of religion may be a bad idea, or at least, a right to be minimized.” One of the key sources of that view, according to Steve's precis of the article, is the relationship of some in the gay rights movement toward religion. Steve closes by suggesting that "[Laycock's] essay should serve as a warning to those who think expressions of concern about religious freedom are trumped up or 'much ado about nothing,'" and by arguing that "[o]ne lesson I would draw (and that Doug in fact draws) is that the problem of articulating persuasive justifications for religious freedom is not just an academic exercise."
In response, Marc DeGirolami wonders whether it is "true that what is needed are new justifications for religious liberty -- new philosophical defenses, updated for the problems and opinions of today," or whether "the fundamental disagreements that we have [are] at bottom matters of intuition, identity, group loyalty, and emotion, and therefore often largely impervious to and unconcerned with the type of high-conceptual discourse that is so central to the academic enterprise." He adds: "Again, if the issue is persuasion, what is the most effective method of achieving it?" I offer my own take below.
For outsiders to the conversation, it is true that there have been some very valuable recent works by Brian Leiter, Micah Schwartzman, and others that question whether religion can really be said to be special or distinct as a principled matter. (And there have been responses too, including a forthcoming book by Andrew Koppelman.) They pose hard questions to supporters of the theory of religious freedom, especially regarding the breadth of freedom of conscience. But I am closer to Marc in my views on how much these arguments really have to do with "expressions of concern about religious freedom" or the state of religious freedom on the ground, for two reasons. First, those arguments about whether religion is unique or not operate at a high level of principle. They generally abstract away from both doctrine and, especially, history and text. They raise hard questions about whether religious freedom, as a matter of pure principle, can be justified as a unique matter, but even on their own terms they do not require us to jettison religious freedom as a practical and doctrinal matter. (And, in my view, they are only very dimly related to the on-the-ground discussions these days, sparked by things such as the contraception mandate, about whether religious freedom in the United States is under threat these days.)
Second, those discussions have taken place within the field of law and religion scholarship, not outside it. They are very much a part of the discussion, not apart from it. Whatever philosophical challenge they pose to religious freedom as a unique thing, they remain constructive and involved, not indifferent or oppositional. By contrast, some of the most fervent academic attacks on religious freedom have taken place outside the conversation altogether. The assignment of labor in the legal academy often creates cloisters and false pictures. In this case, the result of that division is that some of the most stringent conversations about, say, religion versus gay rights have taken place with few or no academics who take religious freedom seriously in the room--sometimes deliberately so. (And sometimes there have been similar responses on the other side.) Some of those conversations operate from such different premises that it is hard to say they have been influenced by work like Leiter's or Schwartzman's; indeed, I doubt that some of the hardline opponents of religious freedom in the gay rights scholarship have even read those pieces, and they certainly haven't engaged with them.
In short, I doubt that Steve is right that the kinds of discussions law and religion scholars have been having lately about whether religious freedom exists as a distinct principle say anything about the broader question of the status of religious freedom today. The real problem is that there have been two very distinct discussions taking place in two different places, in virtually sealed rooms, having little to do with each other. If that's right, Marc's question--"if the issue is persuasion, what is the most effective method of achieving it?"--is all the more pressing. On both sides, there are those who think persuasion is a non-issue because any conversation is pointless.
On this point, I would add two final things. First, not everyone thinks discussions between these two somewhat distinct groups are impossible or fruitless; prominent among them is Doug Laycock himself, who has been involved in efforts to bring both sides together in conversation.
Second, though, as I wrote in one of my earlier posts cited above, those constructive discussions have been between moderates, not between the real polar opposites--those who think it isn't worth discussing religious freedom at all, and those who think that any "'grand bargain'" between the contending sides "is an illusion we should dismiss from our minds." There are genuinely illiberal supporters of gay rights and genuinely illiberal supporters of religious freedom, both in the academy and certainly outside it. For these groups, it may be that "persuasion" is a lost cause; they may have little interest in carrying out conversations in the same room at all. But I think that instead of having only slightly disquieting conversations with folks like Leiter and Schwartzman, who think there are real philosophical problems with religious freedom but are still very much a part of the religious freedom discussion, we religious freedom scholars need to open up the room, even to those who disdain "the liberal apologetics that passes for academic engagement of religion these days." It is possible that mutual engagement will fail utterly. But failing to try, it seems to me, will both make the religious freedom discussion deceptively easy, because it won't reflect some very basic views and facts in the world, and make it all too much of an "academic exercise."
Posted by Paul Horwitz on July 12, 2012 at 08:54 AM in Paul Horwitz | Permalink
TrackBack
TrackBack URL for this entry:
https://www.typepad.com/services/trackback/6a00d8341c6a7953ef01761663cee0970c
Listed below are links to weblogs that reference Is Religious Liberty Vulnerable, or is Religious Liberty Talk Too Insulated?:
Comments
In defense of irreligious liberty (via the First Amendment's speech/press clauses), Higgs confirmation (?) says matter has mass. Does God have mass (other than in the form of religious services)? So what does matter? Well, there is always doubt, whether of the Big Bang, God or Higgs' particle. There should be no war against religion, even though religion often has entered into wars. Any right to proselytize should not trump a right not to be proselytized. Amen.
Posted by: Shag from Brookline | Jul 13, 2012 6:54:10 AM
It never ceases to amaze me that there are those who claim, that because we cannot see God, God does not exist, and yet they claim that The Universe started with a Big Bang, even though it is a self-evident truth, if God created The Universe with a Big Bang, no one but God would have been around to see and hear it.
Posted by: N.D. | Jul 12, 2012 5:02:05 PM
Religious liberty in Amerika is sorely lacking. We will not achieve it until we see atheist chaplains in the military, hospitals and prisons. Until we grant libertarians conscientious objection rights to be free of Obamacare, as the Muslims and Amish are. Until we throw the god words out of the coins, bills, pledges, anthems and Constitution of Texas and other states. Until we eliminate the pervasive and futile prayers and references to god in political congresses at all levels.
The war against religion and other superstitions has yet to begin.
Posted by: Jimbino | Jul 12, 2012 1:41:39 PM
"[f]or the first time in nearly 300 years"
Really? On the cusp of history! Sounds to me that the debates is a matter of line drawing and breadth, which is far from novel. "Religion" itself was defined more narrowly by many people in the past and what is protected by "free exercise" -- valid or not -- has been expanded.
Sounds like the breadth of religious exemptions etc. has led to concerns about balancing the lines some. This doesn't seem particularly novel though I might be missing the whole story in some fashion.
Posted by: Joe | Jul 12, 2012 11:40:20 AM
With the "God Particle" now confirming (?) Higgs, let's expand a song of yore: "Love Makes the Universe Go Round."
Posted by: Shag from Brookline | Jul 12, 2012 11:11:55 AM
Only The True God can endow us with our inherent Right to Religious Liberty. We exist because Perfect Love, The True God, exists. Love exists in relationship. Love is not possessive, nor is it coercive, nor does it serve to manipulate for the sake of self gratification. Love desires that which is Good for one's beloved by respecting the self evident truth, that from The Beginning, every human individual has been created equal in Dignity while being complementary as male and female. We are husbands and wives, fathers and mothers, sons and daughters, brothers and sisters. Our Founding Fathers recognized that God exist, and so they protected our inherent Right to Religious Liberty because they knew that through knowing, Loving, and serving God, we would enhance the value of The State. Today, Religious Liberty is under attack because authentic Love, God, is under attack.
Posted by: N.D. | Jul 12, 2012 10:32:25 AM
I agree that an argument like Brian Leiter's is not clearly related to the problems some gay rights proponents have with religious liberty claims. Quite aside from the sociology of the academic discussions on these topics, simply as a matter of theory, the implications of Leiter's argument mainly serve to complicate the non-discrimination v. religious liberty debate rather than to clearly favor either side. Leiter resists the idea that there is anything special about religion, as opposed to conscience generally, that justifies treating it as special under law. But it is easy enough to frame an objection to, e.g., mandating that wedding photographers photograph same-sex commitment ceremonies as a matter of conscience rather than a matter of specifically religious liberty. While you could use this as a sort of reductio ad absurdum argument against religious exemptions, you could also use it as an argument for broadening them to cover conscience objections broadly. The legal specialness of religion that Leiter criticizes is part of what allows the logic of such exemptions to be compartmentalized.
Posted by: JHW | Jul 12, 2012 10:07:50 AM
Paul, thanks for this. I guess one possible effect or impact of the justification scholarship might be indirect. These sorts of arguments are now in the air, and are therefore part of the background against which the current policy fights of one kind or another are played out. Even if this literature is not being actively consumed by various sorts of combatants, the ways in which ideas might matter or affect the future can be difficult to trace out and predict beforehand. It might also be that one can never be sure which leads -- the social change or the ideas justifying it. Probably it's a complicated association.
Marc
Posted by: Marc DeGirolami | Jul 12, 2012 10:03:04 AM
The comments to this entry are closed.