« Citation counts and the philosophy of law | Main | In Honor of Halloween »
Monday, October 29, 2007
Misguidedly Merciful? A Reply to Professor Meyer (Part 1)
In The Merciful State, Meyer argues that a state that embraces mercy
within its legal institutions of punishment can still be an attractive one
worthy of approbation. Though I largely disagree with that claim on account of
mercy’s inconsistency with retributive justice, I don’t wish to use this space
to elaborate much upon whether mercy is something attractive state institutions
should pursue. For the most part,
readers will be able to see the nature of the disagreement by reading both
pieces and determining for themselves which views about mercy for which they
feel more affinity. Instead, what I’d like to focus on here in this essay
is the way in which Professor Meyer motivates her defense of mercy by attacking
arguments I make on behalf of retributive punishment.
To my mind, Professor Meyer’s criticisms are
largely unfounded, consisting either of mistaken readings of what I wrote or
unpersuasive challenges on the merits. Because enough mischaracterizations in
Professor Meyer’s article exist to raise the worry that others might understand
my views contrary to how I meant them, I will briefly respond to Professor
Meyer’s criticisms in a way that I hope might serve to better illuminate my
account of retributive punishment and what its implications are for the role of
mercy in a liberal democracy. I will lay out these issues over the course of a few separate blog posts.
Let me preface this critique by
noting that, at a high level of generality, Professor Meyer starts well enough.
She correctly writes that I argued that mercy -- defined in my project as leniency
remitted in the realm of punishment, granted out of compassion, corruption,
caprice or bias -- should play no part in state punishment. She also correctly notes that, consistent
with this normative view, I argue that liberal states should be chary of
current practices thought to be constitutional, because they endow various
actors in the criminal justice system with unreviewable discretion to dispense
such mercy. This opposition to mercy is predicated on the view that mercy is
inconsistent not only with retributivism, properly understood, but also with
liberalism, specifically the liberal principle that recognizes all citizens as
possessing an equal package of basic liberties under the law.
What follows over the next few posts is a bill of
particulars that largely follows Professor Meyer’s claims about my work through
her essay. To be clear, some of what follows is a response to good faith but
unpersuasive challenges, while other points I make are based on what I view as
straightforward misreadings of what I wrote. I will try to make obvious which
are which. Separate posts will sketch out some answers to other questions raised by Professor Meyer's article, but I will begin with answers to the following two questions raised by Professor Meyer.
1. Is Retributivism Simply Reducible to
Expressive Utilities?
In the account of retributive
punishment I’ve been developing over the last ten years, one of the reasons I use
to explain the internal intelligibility of retributive punishment is that such
punishment communicates the norm of personal accountability to offenders. The
state communicates its commitment to this norm to the offender when the state attempts
to detect, prosecute, and punish one’s violations of the law through coercive
measures conventionally associated with punishment following adjudication.
Professor Meyer begins her critique
of my account of retributivism by looking at this issue. She notes that “With respect to moral
accountability, many writers have elsewhere argued that ‘expressivist’
retributivist theories like Markel’s that rely on ‘sending a message’ to the
offender or polity tend to reduce to utilitarian arguments about how best to
transmit messages about law and order. One can argue, for example, that
‘sending a message’ would be better achieved via an ad campaign, or via public
corporal punishment, or via punishing only the most famous, only those with
community ties, or only those whose associates and victims are paying
attention.”[4]
Put simply, my account is able to
resist the claim that retributive punishment is simply reducible to the goal of
maximizing general awareness of “law and order.” Indeed, I have actually addressed this exact
point on several occasions.[5] Unlike the unnamed “expressivist theories” Meyer
vaguely alludes to, the focus for my theory is on providing a justification for
the coercion the state imposes on the offender as a result of an encounter
between the state and the offender through the institutions of adjudication and
punishment. In other words, the theory tries to explain how coercive punishment
communicates certain values to the
person most in need of being connected to those values: the offender. If the offender fails to understand the basis
for that communication (say for example because of mental incompetence) then
there is no basis for punishment qua retribution. This is what makes my account of
retributivism a “confrontational” conception of retributivism. A different way
of looking at it is by distinguishing communicative accounts of punishment,
where the primary emphasis is on the relationship between offender and state, and
expressivist accounts of punishment, where the concern is to emit “expressive”
messages to the public at large; those expressive emissions, on my account, are
valuable but they arise incidentally to the confrontational relationship
between state and offender. Thus, the account of retributive punishment I offer
simply cannot be conflated with the goal of ensuring adequate and effective
message dissemination to the public at large.
As I explain in Against Mercy and elsewhere, the expressive messages to the public are not sufficient justification for retributive punishment itself. As Professor Meyer and others note, if the goal is simply to emit messages to the public, it wouldn’t conceptually require punishment as the modus operandi. That’s not to deny punishment’s capacity for norm-projection, but it is to deny that my account of punishment is predicated strictly on that goal.
2. Is Humane Treatment of Offenders an
Undeserved Mercy?
À I am grateful to Ethan Leib, Linda Ross Meyer, Austin Sarat, Jonathan Simon, and Bob Weisberg for comments and conversations about this paper. I sent a version of this paper to Professor Meyer prior to posting and she graciously conceded many of the points here, though she quite understandably retained most of her enthusiasm for the larger project of the “merciful state.” Professor Meyer also raised some interesting questions that I may address in later iterations of this reply.
[1] Forgiveness, Mercy, and Clemency, Austin Sarat & Nasser Hussain, eds., Stanford University Press, 2007.
[2] Dan Markel, Against Mercy, 88 Minn.L. Rev. 1421 (2004) (hereinafter “AM”).
[3] See generally Linda Ross Meyer, The Merciful State (hereinafter “TMS”), available at this link. Citations to TMS refer to the online version of the manuscript.
[4] TMS at 20.
[5] Markel, The Justice of Amnesty? Toward a theory of retributivism in recovering
states, 49 U. Toronto L. J. 389, 421-25 (1999);
Markel, Are Shaming Punishments
Beautifully Retributive? Retributivism and the Implications for the Alternative
Sanctions Debate, 54 Vanderbilt L.
Rev. 2157, 2184-2191 (2001) (hereinafter “Markel (2001)”). [7] See TMS at 20.
Id.
[9] See, e.g., AM at 1468.
Posted by Administrators on October 29, 2007 at 09:21 AM in Article Spotlight, Criminal Law, Dan Markel | Permalink
TrackBack
TrackBack URL for this entry:
https://www.typepad.com/services/trackback/6a00d8341c6a7953ef00e54f144af28834
Listed below are links to weblogs that reference Misguidedly Merciful? A Reply to Professor Meyer (Part 1):
Comments
The comments to this entry are closed.